Selected Papers

A user-friendly description of each paper is provided below. A list of all my papers can be found on my CV.

Publications

"Why Blame?" Journal of Political Economy, (2013), 121(6): 1205-1246 (with Mehmet Y. Gurdal and Aldo Rustichini) gated version [My 2009 Job Market Paper]

Idea (not the abstract): Will Ann hold Bob responsible for an event that Ann knows Bob cannot control? Will Ann do this even if doesn't affect her payoffs? An experiment shows that Ann will do so if the event reveals how Ann would have done had Bob chosen otherwise. We argue that this behavior can be viewed as an unconscious manifestation of the informativeness principle from contract theory. A simple delegated expertise model can account for this behavior, under the assumption that people carry over their optimal behavior from the most related environment (salient perturbation).

Intuition: (1) Are you more likely to fire your financial manager if she performs worse than the S&P 500? (2) rational superstition?

Finalist for the 2014 Exeter Prize

Social Risk and the Dimensionality of IntentionsManagement Science, (2017), 121(6): 1205-1246 (with Jeffrey V. Butler) gated version

Idea (not the abstract): People's attitudes towards risk depend on more than consequences and their associated probabilities. People treat risk differently when it is determined by the actions of another human being, rather than a natural source of risk. This is social risk. We predict that people's attitude towards social risk will depend on their perception of intent. We experimentally manipulate the scope for intentional action and find that attitudes towards social risk are influenced by this manipulation. For example, suppose Ann knows that Bob has a conflict of interest; controlling for the probability of an unfavorable outcome, we find that: (1) Ann treats the social risk from Bob as no different than a natural source of risk if Bob is unaware of the conflict, (2) if Bob is aware of the conflict, but cannot properly foresee the consequences of his actions, then Ann views the social risk from Bob's (partially) intentional action as preferable to a natural source of risk.

Working Papers

Surprised by the Gambler's and Hot Hand Fallacies? A Truth in the Law of Small Numbers”, R&R Econometrica, (2015), (with Adam Sanjurjo)

Idea (not the abstract): If you select a flip from a finite sequence coin flips because it is preceded by several heads, then it is more likely to be a tails. Overlooking this fact is the hot hand fallacy fallacy and it invalidates the conclusions of the original hot hand fallacy study (and its replications). When this fact is accounted for, we find that the hot hand is not a cognitive illusion.

new (short) explainer (The Conversation); old (long) explainer (SSRN); top 10 paper of 2015 (SSRN)

"A Bridge from Monty Hall to the Hot Hand: Restricted Choice, Selection Bias, and Empirical Practice", Under Submission, (2016), (with Adam Sanjurjo)

Idea (not the abstract): What does Monty Hall have to do with the hot hand? The Monty Hall problem is a puzzling brain teaser who's solution many have a difficult time accepting. The hot hand selection bias is the critical statistical error found in the original hot hand fallacy study, and it is an error that many have a difficult time accepting. These two difficulties are illuminated by the principle of restricted choice, an intuitive inferential rule from the card game contract bridge. We quantify this principle as the updating factor from the odds formulation of Bayes' rule. We show how restricted choice not only simplifies calculations, but it renders the classic conditional paradoxes intuitive. Importantly, because restricted choice highlights Monty's selection rule, it provides insights into empirically-relevant selection biases.

puzzle #1 (summary); puzzle #2

"A Visible Hand? Betting on the Hot Hand in Gilovich, Vallone, and Tversky (1985)", Under Submission (2017), (with Adam Sanjurjo)

Idea (not the abstract): While the hot hand can no longer be considered an illusion (see above), the idea that players misperceive the hot hand in basketball continues to be supported by the results from an incentivized betting study from Gilovich, Vallone, and Tversky (1985). In particular, players who believe in the hot hand were found to be unable to detect it (or any other exploitable pattern) in shooting performance. We find the analysis in this study to be severely underpowered and its measure of bettors' ability to predict to be misinterpreted. Upon obtaining the raw data and performing a more powered analysis, in contrast with the original results, we find that experts are successful at predicting shot outcomes, and that the effect sizes are considerable.

"Subjective Beliefs and Confidence When Facts are Forgotten", R&R Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, (2017), (with Igor Kopylov)

Abstract: We run several experiments where people bet on propositions (facts) that they cannot recall with certainty. Forgetting is induced via interference tasks and time delays (up to one year). We use betting preferences to define subjects’ revealed beliefs and their confidence in these beliefs. Forgetting makes revealed beliefs less accurate and reduces the subjective confidence metric as well. Moreover, we find a form of comparative ignorance where subjects are more ambiguity averse when they cannot recall the truth rather than never have learnt it before. In a different vein, we identify an overconfidence pattern: on average, subjects overpay for bets on propositions that they believe in, but underpay for the opposite bets. We formulate a two-signal behavioral model of forgetting that generates all of these patterns

"Is the Belief in the Hot Hand a fallacy in the NBA Three Point Shootout?" (2015), (with Adam Sanjurjo)

Abstract: A prominent exhibit of the hot hand fallacy, which can be considered a quasi-replication of Gilovich, Vallone, and Tversky (1985), is the work of Koehler and Conley (2003). Koehler and Conley find no evidence of hot hand shooting in four years (1994-1997) of NBA Three-Point Contest data, despite the well-known beliefs of players, coaches, and fans alike. The NBA's Three-Point Contest has been referred to as an ideal setting to test for the hot hand (Thaler and Sunstein 2008), as it involves elite professional shooters with large incentives, yet shooting in a fairly controlled environment. We improve on the study of Koehler and Conley by instead collecting 31 years of NBA Three-Point Contest television broadcast data (1986-2017), and applying a statistical approach that: (i) is more powered, (ii) uses an improved set of statistical measures, and (iii) corrects for a substantial downward bias that is present in previous estimates of the hot hand effect. In contrast with the original results, but consistent with recent evidence found relating to the classic work Gilovich, Vallone, and Tversky (1985), we find considerable evidence of hot hand shooting in the NBA Three-Point Contest.

"A Cold Shower for the Hot Hand Fallacy", (2014), (with Adam Sanjurjo)

Idea (not the abstract): The Hot Hand Fallacy, the mistaken belief that good outcomes have a tendency to cluster has long been considered a fallacy with important economic consequences. We develop a novel empirical strategy to correct for flaws in previous studies and perform a critical test of the hot hand fallacy in its canonical domain, basketball shooting. We design field experiment, which improves on earlier fields studies, and reveals that the belief in the hot hand is not a fallacy: hot hand shooting exists across all extant controlled shooting studies and expert decision makers can predict which shooters have a tendency to become hot. In light of these results, we call for further studies to investigate the economic relevance of the hot hand fallacy more generally.


"The Weight of Personal Experience: an Experimental Measurement" (2012), (with Zacharias Maniadis)

Idea (not the abstract): We present an experiment to address the question of whether a piece of information is more influential if it comes from experience, rather than from another source. We employ a novel experimental design which controls for the value of information and other potentially important confounding factors present in related studies. Overall, our results show that an event that is personally experienced has a stronger influence on subsequent behavior than an observed event with equally valuable information content. Importantly, in early rounds when information is more valuable from a rational viewpoint, this overweighting of personal experience is not evident.

Non-Academic Writings

"Momentum isn’t magic – vindicating the hot hand with the mathematics of streaks" The Conversation (2017), (with Adam Sanjurjo)

This is an explanation of our hot hand fallacy work intended for the general reader.